There can hardly be a story that does not involve choice. Two gripping ancient narratives, the story of paradise lost and the story of the Trojan War, start with fatal choices. In the first, Adam and Even choose to disobey God and eat the forbidden fruit from the tree of knowledge. In the second, young prince Paris chooses to offer the golden apple to Aphrodite, setting up a sequence of events that will lead to the Trojan War and, maybe, the thousand year-old enmities that have divided people across the Aegean. In our times, choice has been elevated as the supreme value of our consumer culture and the guarantee of our freedom. So is all choice good? What makes it good?
Choice is a ubiquitous feature of modern life. People make
choices the whole time, about what jobs to apply for, about where to go on
holidays, about who to side with in an argument, about whether to buy a new
machine, about the price to charge for their goods and so on. Choice appears to
be everywhere. Many life issues that, in earlier societies, were pre-determined
by social factors, such as who to marry, what career to pursue, what sexual
identity to adopt and so forth, have now come under the remit of free choice.
Choice is also deemed to be a good thing, it is a value. It is the foundation
stone of contemporary freedom, summed up in the consumer’s freedom to choose
what he/she buys without having to offer any explanations (Bauman, 1988). Choices, however, are not
always open; nor does the appearance of choice always indicate the existence of
serious alternatives. Some choices may look more open from the outside than the
inside. Inside the hurly-burly of social and organizational life, many of our actions
appear not to have the character of choice. An outsider may see choices (“You
could leave your job” “You could retrain and start a new career” etc.) where an
insider sees none. Alternatively, an outsider may see compulsion where an
insider sees choice (“I choose to work 16 hours per day”). Choice is
linked with agency. People who are in control of their own destiny are expected
to make choices whereas those who have no choices are seen as failures,
receiving charity and having others make choices on their behalf. This puts
pressure on employees to see themselves as having choices; otherwise they are
owning up to powerlessness.
It is well known that people cannot choose from an infinite
variety of alternatives. Chinese restaurants realized that huge menus raise the
anxiety levels of many of their customers and sensibly offered set menus as a
way of short-circuiting some of this. The concept of bounded rationality
has been used to explain how most choices are made. An individual narrows the
range of alternatives by excluding various possibilities from the start and
then chooses the first alternative that appears to be ‘good enough’, a process
that Herbert Simon (1957) described as ‘satisficing’
rather than optimizing. While rationality plays an important part in some
choices, others appear to be governed by emotional factors, by desire. Many people
may acknowledge that a particular individual offers great prospects as a
marriage partner (handsome, kind and rich) and yet follow the dictates of their
heart and marry someone who appears to promise excitement, passion and risk.
A great deal of research has focused on consumer choice; how
do people come to choose one product rather than another? This is clearly
crucial for any competitive business and is particularly relevant for marketing
and advertising. There is also much discussion of strategic choice, how, in
other words the ruling blocks or coalitions in organization make choices about
the direction in which they wish to steer it. How are alternatives formulated
and how are they evaluated? There is also much interest in how group choices
may differ from individual choices and the extent to which the perception of
risk shapes group decision. A particularly intriguing account of how people in
organizations make decisions is known as the ‘garbage can’ model of choice.
According to this unexpectedly illuminating idea “an organization is a collection of choices
looking for problems, issues and feelings looking for decision situations
in which they might be aired, solutions looking for issues to which they might
be the answer, and decision-makers looking for work.” (Cohen, March, & Olsen, 1972, p. 2, emphasis added). Choice, in this model, is
not the careful and rational process of selection among alternatives but rather
part of an anarchic and almost random process whereby ideas or measures assume
the character of choices when they collide with socially constructed problems.
Choice was not always seen as an unqualified blessing.
Existential theorists from Kierkegaard viewed choice as generating anxiety.
Sartre’s concept of ‘mauvaise foi’ (bad faith) is not so much a state of
inauthenticity as a deliberate denial of choices in order to avoid the anxiety
that accompanies them (1956). Excessive freedom can be
overwhelming. But sometimes, simple choices in conditions of unfreedom can be even
more oppressive. In the film, Sophie’s Choice, a mother is sadistically
forced by a Nazi officer to choose which of her two children will be murdered.
The decision haunts the rest of her life. Likewise, in the novel Roots,
the recaptured slave Kunta Kinte is allowed to choose what form of dreadful
mutilation he will suffer. Such choices have more of the character of
humiliation. But life is full of choices that call for painful and even tragic decisions.
In organizations, managers and employees may be faced with two alternatives
both of which are unpleasant, but are forced to choose between them. An
employee of a pharmaceutical company might be faced with the choice as to
whether to blow the whistle on false research results or collude with the
wrongdoing. Far from being an unalloyed value, therefore, choice must be
approached in a careful and critical manner to identify whether it is free or
not, whether it is enjoyable or not, whether it is meaningful or not, and,
above all, whether it is real or not.
Bauman, Z. 1988. Freedom. Milton Keynes: Open University
Press.
Cohen, M. D., March, J. G., & Olsen,
J. P. 1972. A garbage can model of organizational choice. Administrative Science Quarterly, 17: 1-25.
Sartre, J.-P. 1956. Being and
nothingness: An essay on phenomenological ontology. New York: Philosophical
Library.
Simon, H. A. 1957. Administrative behavior. New York: Macmillan.
View comments